Political jurisprudence

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Political jurisprudence is a legal theory that some judicial decisions are best understood as part of a political process, with judges operating as political actors. That is, judges are sometimes influenced by public opinion, political activists, and government officials, and their work can be understood as a way of legitimizing and institutionalizing the preferences of these political actors.

Description[edit]

According to Professor Martin Shapiro of University of California, Berkeley, who first noted the theory in 1964: "The core of political jurisprudence is a vision of courts as political agencies and judges as political actors." Legal decisions are no longer focused on a judge's analytical analysis (as in Analytical jurisprudence), but rather it is the judges themselves that become the focus for determining how the decision was reached. Political jurisprudence advocates that judges are not machines but are influenced and swayed by the political system and by their own personal beliefs of how the law should be decided. That is not to say necessarily that judges arbitrarily make decisions they personally feel should be right without regard to stare decisis. Instead they are making decisions based on their political, legal, and personal beliefs as it relates to the law. Deeply, and with more implication for the society, the decisions of the judges are not only modified from the politics, but modify itself the politics and the process of law making in a so influential way, that we can say that the policy-making is "judicialized".[1]

Political jurisprudence can also be seen as a discipline of law. Unlike natural law which answers the fundamental law question by placing law as inherent in the hierarchy of nature, political jurisprudence present the answer as being deliberate human political process. Political jurisprudence presents law as a revolving concept which changes due to change in political perspectives.[2]

Macro and micro[edit]

Shapiro noted political jurisprudence as having two wings, the macro wing and the micro wing. The macro wing looks at courts as players in the political process. In their processes of decision making, they entertain matters from different interest groups hence shape policy through pressure from these. the micro wing looks at individual decisions of judges. The second wing is a manifestation of Charles H. Pritchett who introduced behaviorism into USA judicial studies after studies that showed individual decisions in courts have been increasing since the days of President Roosevelt.[3]

Case studies[edit]

The 1953 Pakistani constitutional coup has been presented as an example of political jurisprudence.[citation needed] The Federal Court of Pakistan's 1955 decision in Federation of Pakistan v. Maulvi Tamizuddin Khan gave legitimacy to the coup d’état.[citation needed]

A Turkish judicial decision has also has been presented as an example of political jurisprudence.[citation needed] The Turkish Constitutional Court judged against a constitutional amendment which was procedurally correct.[citation needed]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

References[edit]

  • Loughlin, Martin (July 2016). "Political Jurisprudence". Jus Politicum: International Journal of Political Law (16). ISSN 2105-0937.
  • Rayside, David (June 2006). "Courts, Liberalism and Rights by Jason Pierceson and The Case for Gay Rights by David A.J. Richards". Political Science Quarterly (Book review). 121 (2): 348–351. doi:10.1002/j.1538-165x.2006.tb01509.x.
  • Shapiro, Martin (1963). "Political Jurisprudence". Kentucky Law Journal. 52 (2): 294–345. ISSN 0023-026X.
  • Shapiro, Martin; Stone Sweet, Alec (2002). On Law, Politics, & Judicialization. Oxford University Press.
  • Stone Sweet, Alec (2000). Governing with Judges. Oxford University Press.

Further reading[edit]

  • Devins, Neal; Baum, Lawrence (2019). The Company They Keep: How Partisan Divisions Came to the Supreme Court. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-027805-2.