Martin's axiom

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In the mathematical field of set theory, Martin's axiom, introduced by Donald A. Martin and Robert M. Solovay,[1] is a statement that is independent of the usual axioms of ZFC set theory. It is implied by the continuum hypothesis, but it is consistent with ZFC and the negation of the continuum hypothesis. Informally, it says that all cardinals less than the cardinality of the continuum, , behave roughly like . The intuition behind this can be understood by studying the proof of the Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma. It is a principle that is used to control certain forcing arguments.

Statement[edit]

For any cardinal 𝛋, consider the following statement:

MA(𝛋)
For any partial order P satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter ccc) and any family D of dense subsets of P such that |D| ≤ 𝛋, there is a filter F on P such that Fd is non-empty for every d in D.

In this case (for application of ccc), an antichain is a subset A of P such that any two distinct members of A are incompatible (two elements are said to be compatible if there exists a common element below both of them in the partial order). This differs from, for example, the notion of antichain in the context of trees.

MA(ℵ0) is simply true — the Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma. MA(20) is false: [0, 1] is a separable compact Hausdorff space, and so (P, the poset of open subsets under inclusion, is) ccc. But now consider the following two size-20=c families of dense sets in P: no x∈[0, 1] is isolated, and so each x defines the dense subset {S : xS}. And each r∈(0, 1], defines the dense subset {S : diam(S)<r}. The two families combined are also of size c, and a filter meeting both must simultaneously avoid all points of [0, 1] while containing sets of arbitrarily small diameter. But a filter F containing sets of arbitrarily small diameter must contain a point in ⋂F by compactness. (See also § Equivalent forms of MA(κ).)

Martin's axiom is then that MA(κ) holds "as long as possible":

Martin's axiom (MA)
For every 𝛋 < c, MA(𝛋) holds.

Equivalent forms of MA(𝛋)[edit]

The following statements are equivalent to MA(𝛋):

  • If X is a compact Hausdorff topological space that satisfies the ccc then X is not the union of 𝛋 or fewer nowhere dense subsets.
  • If P is a non-empty upwards ccc poset and Y is a family of cofinal subsets of P with |Y| ≤ 𝛋 then there is an upwards-directed set A such that A meets every element of Y.
  • Let A be a non-zero ccc Boolean algebra and F a family of subsets of A with |F| ≤ 𝛋. Then there is a boolean homomorphism φ: AZ/2Z such that for every X in F either there is an a in X with φ(a) = 1 or there is an upper bound b for X with φ(b) = 0.

Consequences[edit]

Martin's axiom has a number of other interesting combinatorial, analytic and topological consequences:

  • The union of 𝛋 or fewer null sets in an atomless σ-finite Borel measure on a Polish space is null. In particular, the union of 𝛋 or fewer subsets of R of Lebesgue measure 0 also has Lebesgue measure 0.
  • A compact Hausdorff space X with |X| < 2𝛋 is sequentially compact, i.e., every sequence has a convergent subsequence.
  • No non-principal ultrafilter on N has a base of cardinality < 𝛋.
  • Equivalently for any x in βN\N we have 𝜒(x) ≥ 𝛋, where 𝜒 is the character of x, and so 𝜒(βN) ≥ 𝛋.
  • MA(ℵ1) implies that a product of ccc topological spaces is ccc (this in turn implies there are no Suslin lines).
  • MA + ¬CH implies that there exists a Whitehead group that is not free; Shelah used this to show that the Whitehead problem is independent of ZFC.

Further development[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^ Martin, Donald A.; Solovay, Robert M. (1970). "Internal Cohen extensions". Ann. Math. Logic. 2 (2): 143–178. doi:10.1016/0003-4843(70)90009-4. MR 0270904.
  2. ^ Davis, Sheldon W. (2005). Topology. McGraw Hill. p. 29. ISBN 0-07-291006-2.

Further reading[edit]